module Data.Finset.Base where
private variable
: Level
ℓ ℓ' ℓ'' : Type ℓ A B C
Finitely indexed subsets🔗
We define a type of Kuratowski-finite subsets of a type as a higher inductive type mirroring the definition of lists, but with generating equations which allow removing duplicates and reordering elements. Note that we must also truncate the resulting type to make sure we end up with something homotopically coherent.
As the name of the module implies, this is an alternative presentation of Kuratowski finite subsets of i.e. subsets of whose total space admits a surjection from some standard finite set, which makes working with the elements more convenient — as long as we can express the operation we’re doing with the subsets is invariant under repetition and swapping (i.e. we’re mapping into a join semilattice).
infixr 20 _∷_
data Finset {ℓ} (A : Type ℓ) : Type ℓ where
: Finset A
[] _∷_ : (x : A) (xs : Finset A) → Finset A
: ∀ x xs → (x ∷ x ∷ xs) ≡ (x ∷ xs)
∷-dup : ∀ x y xs → (x ∷ y ∷ xs) ≡ (y ∷ x ∷ xs)
∷-swap
: is-set (Finset A) squash
Note that, since these are equations (rather than a separate equivalence relation on lists), we do not need to add path constructors saying that we can reorder elements deep in the list:
private module _ {A : Type ℓ} {w x y z : A} where
_ : Path (Finset A) (w ∷ x ∷ y ∷ z ∷ []) (w ∷ x ∷ y ∷ y ∷ z ∷ [])
_ = ap (λ e → w Finset.∷ x Finset.∷ e) (sym (∷-dup y (z ∷ [])))
Finset-elim-prop: ∀ {ℓ ℓ'} {A : Type ℓ} (P : Finset A → Type ℓ')
→ ⦃ ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄
→ P []
→ (∀ x {xs} → P xs → P (x ∷ xs))
→ ∀ x → P x
= p[]
Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ [] (x ∷ xs) = p∷ x (Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ xs)
Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ (∷-dup x xs i) =
Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ (λ i → hlevel {T = P (∷-dup x xs i)} 1) (p∷ _ (p∷ _ (Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ xs))) (p∷ _ (Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ xs)) i
is-prop→pathp (∷-swap x y xs i) =
Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ (λ i → hlevel {T = P (∷-swap x y xs i)} 1)
is-prop→pathp (p∷ _ (p∷ _ (Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ xs)))
(p∷ _ (p∷ _ (Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ xs))) i
(squash x y p q i j) =
Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ let go = Finset-elim-prop P p[] p∷ in
(λ i j → hlevel {T = P (squash x y p q i j)} 1)
is-prop→squarep (λ i → go x) (λ i → go (p i)) (λ i → go (q i)) (λ i → go y) i j
unquoteDecl Finset-rec = make-rec-n 2 Finset-rec (quote Finset)
instance
: ∀ {n} → H-Level (Finset A) (2 + n)
H-Level-Finset = basic-instance 2 squash
H-Level-Finset
open 1Lab.Reflection using (List ; [] ; _∷_)
Of course, since finite sets and lists have the same point constructors, we can turn any list into a finite set.
: List A → Finset A
from-list = []
from-list [] (x ∷ xs) = x ∷ from-list xs from-list
Moreover, we can show that this function is surjective; this implies that the type of finite sets (over a set is a quotient of the type of lists of
: is-surjective (from-list {A = A})
from-list-is-surjective = Finset-elim-prop _
from-list-is-surjective (inc ([] , refl))
(λ x → rec! λ xs p → inc (x ∷ xs , ap (x ∷_) p))
Basic operations🔗
We can replicate the definition of basic list operations on finite
sets essentially as-is, as long as we can prove that they respect the
generating paths — that is, as long as whatever we choose to “replace
_∷_
with” is also idempotent and allows swapping on the left. For a basic
example, we can swap conses with conses, to implement map
:
: (A → B) → Finset A → Finset B
mapᶠˢ = []
mapᶠˢ f [] (x ∷ xs) = f x ∷ mapᶠˢ f xs
mapᶠˢ f (∷-dup x xs i) = ∷-dup (f x) (mapᶠˢ f xs) i
mapᶠˢ f (∷-swap x y xs i) = ∷-swap (f x) (f y) (mapᶠˢ f xs) i
mapᶠˢ f (squash x y p q i j) = squash (mapᶠˢ f x) (mapᶠˢ f y) (λ i → mapᶠˢ f (p i)) (λ i → mapᶠˢ f (q i)) i j mapᶠˢ f
instance
: Map (eff Finset)
Map-Finset = record { map = mapᶠˢ }
Map-Finset {-# DISPLAY mapᶠˢ f xs = map f xs #-}
We can also implement filter
,
since at the end of the day we’re once again replacing conses with
conses.
: Dec B → A → Finset A → Finset A
cons-if (yes _) x xs = x ∷ xs
cons-if (no _) x xs = xs
cons-if
: (P : A → Type ℓ) ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → Dec (P x) ⦄ → Finset A → Finset A
filter = []
filter f [] (x ∷ xs) = cons-if (holds? (f x)) x (filter f xs)
filter f (∷-dup x xs i) with holds? (f x)
filter f ... | yes _ = ∷-dup x (filter f xs) i
... | no _ = filter f xs
(∷-swap x y xs i) with holds? (f x) | holds? (f y)
filter f ... | yes _ | yes _ = ∷-swap x y (filter f xs) i
... | yes _ | no _ = x ∷ filter f xs
... | no _ | yes _ = y ∷ filter f xs
... | no _ | no _ = filter f xs
(squash x y p q i j) = squash (filter f x) (filter f y) (λ i → filter f (p i)) (λ i → filter f (q i)) i j filter f
Finally, we can implement an append operation — called
union
because of its semantics as a subset — since we’re
keeping all the conses and replacing []
with a different finset.
: Finset A → Finset A → Finset A
union = ys
union [] ys (x ∷ xs) ys = x ∷ union xs ys
union (∷-dup x xs i) ys = ∷-dup x (union xs ys) i
union (∷-swap x y xs i) ys = ∷-swap x y (union xs ys) i
union (squash xs ys p q i j) zs = squash (union xs zs) (union ys zs) (λ i → union (p i) zs) (λ i → union (q i) zs) i j union
instance
: Append (Finset A)
Append-Sub = record { _<>_ = union ; mempty = [] } Append-Sub
Properties of union🔗
One downside of the higher-inductive definition is that if we want to
define operations on finsets which use union
, we’ll have to prove that it
behaves sufficiently like _∷_
.
In particular, we prove that it’s a semilattice, which is
sufficient (though more than necessary) to imply it is idempotent and
allows swapping on the left.
All of these proofs are by induction on the leftmost finite set. Since we’re showing a proposition, it suffices to consider the point constructors, in which case we essentially have the same proofs as for lists (though written in higher-order style).
abstract
: (xs ys zs : Finset A) → xs <> (ys <> zs) ≡ (xs <> ys) <> zs
union-assoc = Finset-elim-prop _
union-assoc (λ ys zs → refl)
(λ x ih ys zs → ap (x ∷_) (ih ys zs))
: (xs : Finset A) → xs <> [] ≡ xs
union-idr = Finset-elim-prop _ refl λ x p → ap (x ∷_) p
union-idr
: (x : A) (xs ys : Finset A) → xs <> (x ∷ ys) ≡ (x ∷ xs) <> ys
union-consr = Finset-elim-prop _ (λ ys → refl)
union-consr x λ y ih ys → ap (y ∷_) (ih ys) ∙ ∷-swap _ _ _
: (xs ys : Finset A) → xs <> ys ≡ ys <> xs
union-comm = Finset-elim-prop _ (λ ys → sym (union-idr ys))
union-comm λ x {xs} ih ys → sym (union-consr x ys xs ∙ ap (x ∷_) (sym (ih ys)))
: (xs : Finset A) → xs <> xs ≡ xs
union-idem = Finset-elim-prop _ refl
union-idem λ x {xs} ih → ap (x ∷_) (union-consr x xs xs) ∙∙ ∷-dup _ _ ∙∙ ap (x ∷_) ih
: (xs ys : Finset A) → xs <> (xs <> ys) ≡ xs <> ys
union-dup = union-assoc xs xs ys ∙ ap (_<> ys) (union-idem xs)
union-dup xs ys
: (xs ys zs : Finset A) → xs <> (ys <> zs) ≡ ys <> (xs <> zs)
union-swap = union-assoc xs ys zs ∙∙ ap (_<> zs) (union-comm xs ys) ∙∙ sym (union-assoc ys xs zs) union-swap xs ys zs
More basic operations🔗
With these paths in hand, we can prove that Finset
is a monad on sets. First, we show
how to flatten a finite set of finite sets, by applying iterated
unions.
: Finset (Finset A) → Finset A
concat = []
concat [] (x ∷ xs) = x <> concat xs
concat (∷-dup x xs i) = union-dup x (concat xs) i
concat (∷-swap x y xs i) = union-swap x y (concat xs) i
concat (squash x y p q i j) = squash
concat (concat x) (concat y) (λ i → concat (p i)) (λ i → concat (q i)) i j
We can then define a couple more operations familiar to functional programmers.
_<*>ᶠˢ_ : Finset (A → B) → Finset A → Finset B
= []
[] <*>ᶠˢ xs (f ∷ fs) <*>ᶠˢ xs = mapᶠˢ f xs <> (fs <*>ᶠˢ xs)
= union-dup (map f xs) (fs <*>ᶠˢ xs) i
∷-dup f fs i <*>ᶠˢ xs = union-swap (map f xs) (map g xs) (fs <*>ᶠˢ xs) i
∷-swap f g fs i <*>ᶠˢ xs = squash
squash f g p q i j <*>ᶠˢ xs (f <*>ᶠˢ xs) (g <*>ᶠˢ xs) (λ i → p i <*>ᶠˢ xs) (λ i → q i <*>ᶠˢ xs) i j
_>>=ᶠˢ_ : Finset A → (A → Finset B) → Finset B
= []
[] >>=ᶠˢ f (x ∷ xs) >>=ᶠˢ f = f x <> (xs >>=ᶠˢ f)
= union-dup (f x) (xs >>=ᶠˢ f) i
∷-dup x xs i >>=ᶠˢ f = union-swap (f x) (f y) (xs >>=ᶠˢ f) i
∷-swap x y xs i >>=ᶠˢ f = squash
squash x y p q i j >>=ᶠˢ f (x >>=ᶠˢ f) (y >>=ᶠˢ f) (λ i → p i >>=ᶠˢ f) (λ i → q i >>=ᶠˢ f) i j
: {P : A → Type ℓ} → Finset A → (∀ x → Finset (P x)) → Finset (Σ A P)
sigma = []
sigma [] f (x ∷ xs) f = map (x ,_) (f x) <> sigma xs f
sigma (∷-dup x xs i) f = union-dup (map (x ,_) (f x)) (sigma xs f) i
sigma (∷-swap x y xs i) f = union-swap (map (x ,_) (f x)) (map (y ,_) (f y)) (sigma xs f) i
sigma (squash x y p q i j) f = squash (sigma x f) (sigma y f) (λ i → sigma (p i) f) (λ i → sigma (q i) f) i j
sigma
instance
: Idiom (eff Finset)
Idiom-Finset = record { pure = _∷ [] ; _<*>_ = _<*>ᶠˢ_ }
Idiom-Finset
: Bind (eff Finset)
Bind-Sub .Bind._>>=_ xs f = snd <$> sigma xs f
Bind-Sub .Bind.Idiom-bind = Idiom-Finset
Bind-Sub
{-# DISPLAY _<*>ᶠˢ_ fs xs = fs <*> xs #-}
Membership🔗
private
abstract
: (P Q : Type ℓ) → ∥ P ⊎ ∥ P ⊎ Q ∥ ∥ ≡ ∥ P ⊎ Q ∥
dup = ua $ prop-ext!
dup P Q (_>>= λ { (inl x) → inc (inl x) ; (inr x) → x })
(_>>= λ { (inl x) → inc (inl x) ; (inr x) → inc (inr (inc (inr x))) })
: (P Q R : Type ℓ) → ∥ P ⊎ ∥ Q ⊎ R ∥ ∥ ≡ ∥ Q ⊎ ∥ P ⊎ R ∥ ∥
swap = ua $ prop-ext!
swap P Q R (_>>= λ where
(inl x) → inc (inr (inc (inl x)))
(inr x) → x >>= λ where
(inl x) → inc (inl x)
(inr x) → inc (inr (inc (inr x))))
(_>>= λ where
(inl x) → inc (inr (inc (inl x)))
(inr x) → x >>= λ where
(inl x) → inc (inl x)
(inr x) → inc (inr (inc (inr x))))
We now show how to define membership for finite sets. Since we have
to map into a set (to handle the squash
constructor), we have to make the
result a proposition. Therefore, the definition of
has to be truncated.
: A → Finset A → Prop (level-of A)
finset-mem .∣_∣ = Lift _ ⊥
finset-mem x [] (y ∷ xs) .∣_∣ = ∥ (x ≡ᵢ y) ⊎ ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟ ∥
finset-mem x (∷-dup y xs i) .∣_∣ = dup (x ≡ᵢ y) ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟ i
finset-mem x (∷-swap y z xs i) .∣_∣ = swap (x ≡ᵢ y) (x ≡ᵢ z) ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟ i finset-mem x
.is-tr = hlevel 1
finset-mem x [] (y ∷ xs) .is-tr = squash
finset-mem x (∷-swap y z xs i) .is-tr = is-prop→pathp
finset-mem x (λ i → is-prop-is-prop {A = swap (x ≡ᵢ y) (x ≡ᵢ z) ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟ i}) squash squash i
(∷-dup y xs i) .is-tr = is-prop→pathp
finset-mem x (λ i → is-prop-is-prop {A = dup (x ≡ᵢ y) ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟ i}) squash squash i
(squash xs ys p q i j) =
finset-mem x 1
n-Type-is-hlevel (finset-mem x xs) (finset-mem x ys)
(λ i → finset-mem x (p i)) (λ i → finset-mem x (q i)) i j
opaque_∈ᶠˢ_ : A → Finset A → Type (level-of A)
= ⌞ finset-mem x xs ⌟
x ∈ᶠˢ xs
: ∀ {x y : A} {xs} → x ≡ᵢ y → x ∈ᶠˢ (y ∷ xs)
hereₛ' = inc (inl p)
hereₛ' p
: ∀ {x y : A} {xs} → y ∈ᶠˢ xs → y ∈ᶠˢ (x ∷ xs)
thereₛ = inc (inr x)
thereₛ x
: {x : A} → ¬ (x ∈ᶠˢ [])
¬mem-[] ()
¬mem-[]
private
: {x : A} {xs : Finset A} → ⊤ → is-prop (x ∈ᶠˢ xs)
∈ᶠˢ-hlevel {x = x} {xs} _ = finset-mem x xs .is-tr
∈ᶠˢ-hlevel
: ∀ {x : A} {xs} → x ∈ᶠˢ (x ∷ xs)
hereₛ = hereₛ' reflᵢ
hereₛ
instance
: hlevel-projection (quote _∈ᶠˢ_)
hlevel-proj-∈ᶠˢ .hlevel-projection.has-level = quote ∈ᶠˢ-hlevel
hlevel-proj-∈ᶠˢ .hlevel-projection.get-level x = pure (lit (nat 1))
hlevel-proj-∈ᶠˢ .hlevel-projection.get-argument x = pure (con₀ (quote tt))
hlevel-proj-∈ᶠˢ
: Membership A (Finset A) _
Membership-Finset = record { _∈_ = _∈ᶠˢ_ }
Membership-Finset
: Underlying (Finset A)
Underlying-Finset = record { ⌞_⌟ = ∫ₚ } Underlying-Finset
We can then define a case analysis principle for membership in a finite set, as long as we’re showing a proposition.
opaque_∈ᶠˢ_
unfolding
∈ᶠˢ-split: ∀ {ℓp} {x y : A} {xs} {P : x ∈ᶠˢ (y ∷ xs) → Type ℓp} ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄
→ ((p : x ≡ᵢ y) → P (hereₛ' p))
→ ((w : x ∈ᶠˢ xs) → P (thereₛ w))
→ (w : x ∈ᶠˢ (y ∷ xs)) → P w
= ∥-∥-elim (λ x → hlevel 1 ⦃ h ⦄) λ where
∈ᶠˢ-split ⦃ h ⦄ l r (inl a) → l a
(inr b) → r b
∈ᶠˢ-split-here: ∀ {ℓp} {x y : A} {xs} {P : Type ℓp} ⦃ _ : H-Level P 1 ⦄ {p : x ≡ᵢ y} (f : x ≡ᵢ y → P) (g : x ∈ᶠˢ xs → P)
→ ∈ᶠˢ-split {xs = xs} f g (hereₛ' p) ≡ f p
= refl
∈ᶠˢ-split-here f g
∈ᶠˢ-split-there: ∀ {ℓp} {x y : A} {xs} {P : Type ℓp} ⦃ _ : H-Level P 1 ⦄ (f : x ≡ᵢ y → P) (g : x ∈ᶠˢ xs → P) (w : x ∈ᶠˢ xs)
→ ∈ᶠˢ-split {y = y} {xs = xs} f g (thereₛ w) ≡ g w
= refl
∈ᶠˢ-split-there f g w
{-# REWRITE ∈ᶠˢ-split-here ∈ᶠˢ-split-there #-}
: (d : Dec B) (x y : A) (xs : Finset A) → y ∈ xs → y ∈ cons-if d x xs
there-cons-if (yes a) x y xs p = thereₛ p
there-cons-if (no ¬a) x y xs p = p
there-cons-if
∈ᶠˢ-case: ∀ {ℓp} {x y : A} {xs} {P : Type ℓp} ⦃ _ : H-Level P 1 ⦄
→ (w : x ∈ᶠˢ (y ∷ xs)) → ((p : x ≡ᵢ y) → P) → ((w : x ∈ᶠˢ xs) → P) → P
{P = P} w f g = ∈ᶠˢ-split {P = λ _ → P} f g w ∈ᶠˢ-case
Putting this together with induction over finite sets, we can show that the membership type behaves as though it were an inductive family.
∈ᶠˢ-elim: ∀ {ℓp} {x : A} (P : ∀ xs → x ∈ᶠˢ xs → Type ℓp) ⦃ _ : ∀ {xs p} → H-Level (P xs p) 1 ⦄
→ (∀ {xs} → P (x ∷ xs) hereₛ)
→ (∀ {y xs} q → P xs q → P (y ∷ xs) (thereₛ q))
→ ∀ xs w → P xs w
{x = x} P phere pthere xs w = Finset-elim-prop (λ xs → (w : x ∈ᶠˢ xs) → P xs w)
∈ᶠˢ-elim (λ m → absurd (¬mem-[] m))
(λ y {xs'} ind → ∈ᶠˢ-split {P = P (y ∷ xs')}
(λ { reflᵢ → phere })
λ w → pthere w (ind w))
xs w
Over discrete types🔗
We’ll show that membership in a finite set is decidable, as long as the type of elements is discrete. First, note that we’re showing a proposition, so all the path cases will be automatic.
instance
: ⦃ _ : Discrete A ⦄ {x : A} {xs : Finset A} → Dec (x ∈ xs)
Dec-∈ᶠˢ {A = A} ⦃ eq ⦄ {x = x} {xs} = go xs where
Dec-∈ᶠˢ abstract
: (xs : Finset A) → is-prop (Dec (x ∈ xs))
p = hlevel 1 p xs
We’ll start with our inductive case: if we’re looking at a finite set of the form we can put together a decision for out of a decision for whether and a decision for whether
cons-mem: (y : A) (xs : Finset A)
→ Dec (x ≡ᵢ y)
→ Dec ⌞ x ∈ xs ⌟
→ Dec ⌞ x ∈ (y ∷ xs) ⌟
Note that, even though may also appear in if it’s at the head position, we’ll always return the “earlier” proof of membership — this matters when computing, even though we’re dealing with propositions!.
(yes p) _ = yes (hereₛ' p)
cons-mem y xs (no ¬p) (yes p) = yes (thereₛ p)
cons-mem y xs (no ¬p) (no ¬q) = no (∈ᶠˢ-split ¬p ¬q) cons-mem y xs
Finally, the base case is automatic: there are no elements in the empty finite set.
: (xs : Finset A) → Dec (x ∈ xs)
go = Finset-elim-prop _
go (no ¬mem-[])
(λ y {xs} rest → cons-mem y xs (x ≡ᵢ? y) rest)
Cardinality🔗
To close out this basic module, we show how to count the elements of
a finite set. In a list, you simply count the number of _∷_
constructors, but here, we must respect duplicates and swaps. This means
that, at each element, we must only add one to the count if the element
does not appear in the tail of the list. This implies that we can only
count the number of elements in a finite set with discrete carrier; it
also implies that computing the size of a Finset
is
quadratic in the number of equality tests.
module _ {A : Type ℓ} ⦃ d : Discrete A ⦄ where
: Finset A → Nat
count
private
: (x : A) (xs : Finset A) → Dec (x ∈ xs)
has = holds? (x ∈ xs)
has x xs
: A → Finset A → Nat
cons = Dec-rec (λ _ → count xs) (λ _ → suc (count xs)) (has x xs)
cons x xs
: ∀ x xs → cons x (x ∷ xs) ≡ cons x xs
cons-dup : ∀ x y xs → cons x (y ∷ xs) ≡ cons y (x ∷ xs)
cons-swap
= 0
count [] (x ∷ xs) = cons x xs
count (∷-dup x xs i) = cons-dup x xs i
count (∷-swap x y xs i) = cons-swap x y xs i
count (squash x y p q i j) = hlevel 2 (count x) (count y) (λ i → count (p i)) (λ i → count (q i)) i j count
Showing the necessary respect for the generating equations boils down to a billion case splits.
with has x xs
cons-dup x xs | yes p with has x (x ∷ xs)
cons-dup x xs | yes p | yes q = refl
cons-dup x xs | yes p | no ¬p = absurd (¬p hereₛ)
cons-dup x xs | no ¬p with has x (x ∷ xs)
cons-dup x xs | no ¬p | yes q = refl
cons-dup x xs | no ¬p | no ¬q = absurd (¬q hereₛ)
cons-dup x xs
with has x (y ∷ xs) | has y (x ∷ xs) | has x xs | has y xs
cons-swap x y xs ... | yes p | yes q | yes r | yes s = refl
... | yes p | yes q | no ¬r | no ¬s = refl
... | yes p | no ¬q | yes r | no ¬s = refl
... | no ¬p | yes q | no ¬r | yes s = refl
... | no ¬p | no ¬q | yes r | yes s = refl
... | no ¬p | no ¬q | no ¬r | no ¬s = refl
... | yes p | yes q | yes r | no ¬s = ∈ᶠˢ-split (λ { reflᵢ → absurd (¬s r) }) (λ w → absurd (¬s w)) q
... | yes p | yes q | no ¬r | yes s = ∈ᶠˢ-split (λ { reflᵢ → absurd (¬r s) }) (λ w → absurd (¬r w)) p
... | yes p | no ¬q | yes r | yes s = absurd (¬q (thereₛ s))
... | yes p | no ¬q | no ¬r | yes s = absurd (¬q (thereₛ s))
... | yes p | no ¬q | no ¬r | no ¬s = ∈ᶠˢ-split (λ { reflᵢ → absurd (¬q p) }) (λ w → absurd (¬r w)) p
... | no ¬p | yes q | yes r | yes s = ∈ᶠˢ-split (λ { reflᵢ → absurd (¬p q) }) (λ w → absurd (¬p ((thereₛ r)))) q
... | no ¬p | yes q | yes r | no ¬s = absurd (¬p (thereₛ r))
... | no ¬p | yes q | no ¬r | no ¬s = ∈ᶠˢ-split (λ { reflᵢ → absurd (¬p q) }) (λ w → absurd (¬s w)) q
... | no ¬p | no ¬q | yes r | no ¬s = absurd (¬p (thereₛ r))
... | no ¬p | no ¬q | no ¬r | yes s = absurd (¬q (thereₛ s))
: ⦃ _ : Discrete A ⦄ → Finset A → Finset A → Finset A
intersection = []
intersection [] ys (x ∷ xs) ys = cons-if (holds? (x ∈ ys)) x (intersection xs ys)
intersection (∷-dup x xs i) ys with holds? (x ∈ ys)
intersection ... | yes p = ∷-dup x (intersection xs ys) i
... | no ¬p = intersection xs ys
(∷-swap x y xs i) ys with holds? (x ∈ ys) | holds? (y ∈ ys)
intersection ... | yes a | yes b = ∷-swap x y (intersection xs ys) i
... | yes a | no ¬b = x ∷ intersection xs ys
... | no ¬a | yes b = y ∷ intersection xs ys
... | no ¬a | no ¬b = intersection xs ys
(squash a b p q i j) ys = squash (intersection a ys) (intersection b ys) (λ i → intersection (p i) ys) (λ i → intersection (q i) ys) i j
intersection
: (P : A → Type ℓ) ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄ → Finset A → Prop ℓ
finset-all = el! (Lift _ ⊤)
finset-all P [] (x ∷ xs) = el! (P x × ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟)
finset-all P (∷-dup x xs i) = n-ua {X = el! (P x × P x × ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟)} {Y = el! (P x × ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟)} (prop-ext! snd λ (a , b) → a , a , b) i
finset-all P (∷-swap x y xs i) = n-ua {X = el! (P x × P y × ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟)} {Y = el! (P y × P x × ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟)} (prop-ext! (λ (a , b , c) → b , a , c) (λ (a , b , c) → b , a , c)) i
finset-all P (squash x y p q i j) = hlevel 2 (finset-all P x) (finset-all P y) (λ i → finset-all P (p i)) (λ i → finset-all P (q i)) i j
finset-all P
opaque: (P : A → Type ℓ) ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄ → Finset A → Type ℓ
All = ⌞ finset-all P xs ⌟
All P xs
private
: ∀ {P : A → Type ℓ} ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄ {xs : Finset A} → ⊤ → is-prop (All P xs)
all-hlevel {P = P} {xs = xs} tt = finset-all P xs .is-tr
all-hlevel
instance
: hlevel-projection (quote All)
hlevel-proj-all .hlevel-projection.has-level = quote all-hlevel
hlevel-proj-all .hlevel-projection.get-level x = pure (lit (nat 1))
hlevel-proj-all .hlevel-projection.get-argument x = pure (con₀ (quote tt))
hlevel-proj-all
module _ {P : A → Type ℓ} ⦃ _ : ∀ {x} → H-Level (P x) 1 ⦄ where opaque
unfolding All
: {x : A} {xs : Finset A} → P x → All P xs → All P (x ∷ xs)
all-cons = _,_
all-cons
: All P []
all-nil = lift tt
all-nil
: (xs : Finset A) → (∀ x → x ∈ xs → P x) → All P xs
to-all = Finset-elim-prop _ (λ _ → lift tt) (λ x {xs} ind w → w x hereₛ , ind (λ x xs → w x (thereₛ xs)))
to-all
: {x : A} (xs : Finset A) → All P xs → x ∈ xs → P x
from-all {x = x} xs all elt =
from-all (λ xs _ → All P xs → P x) fst (λ _ ind (_ , a) → ind a) xs elt all
∈ᶠˢ-elim
{-# DISPLAY all-cons x xs = x ∷ xs #-}
{-# DISPLAY all-nil = [] #-}