module Cat.Functor.Hom.Representable {o κ} {C : Precategory o κ} where
Representable functors🔗
A functor (from a locally category) is said to be representable when it is naturally isomorphic to for an object (called the representing object) — that is, the functor classifies the maps into Note that we can evidently dualise the definition, to get what is called a corepresentable functor, one of the form but we refer informally to both of these situations as “representables” and “representing objects”.
record Representation (F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)) : Type (o ⊔ κ) where
no-eta-equality
field
: C.Ob
rep : F ≅ⁿ Hom-into C rep
represents
module rep = Isoⁿ represents
: ∀ {a} → C.Hom a rep ≃ F ʻ a
equiv = Equiv.inverse (natural-iso→equiv represents _)
equiv
module Rep {a} = Equiv (equiv {a})
open Representation
open Representation using (module Rep) public
This definition is deceptively simple: the idea of representable functor (and of representing object) is key to understanding the idea of universal property, which could be called the most important concept in category theory. Most constructions in category theory specified in terms of the existence of certain maps are really instances of representing objects for functors: limits, colimits, coends, adjoint functors, Kan extensions, etc.
The first thing we will observe is an immediate consequence of the Yoneda lemma: representing objects are unique. Intuitively this is because “ is a representation of ” determines how reacts to being mapped into, and since the only thing we can probe objects in an arbitrary category by are morphisms, two objects which react to morphisms in the same way must be isomorphic.
: {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)} (X Y : Representation F)
representation-unique → X .rep C.≅ Y .rep
=
representation-unique X Y {F = よ C} (よ-is-fully-faithful C) よX≅よY where
is-ff→essentially-injective : よ₀ C (X .rep) C^.≅ よ₀ C (Y .rep)
よX≅よY = (X .represents C^.Iso⁻¹) C^.∘Iso Y .represents よX≅よY
Therefore, if is a univalent category, then the type of representations for a functor is a proposition. This does not follow immediately from the lemma above: we also need to show that the isomorphism computed by the full-faithfulness of the Yoneda embedding commutes with the specified representation isomorphism. This follows by construction, but the proof needs to commute applications of functors and paths-from-isos, which is never pretty:
: ∀ {F} → is-category C → is-prop (Representation F)
Representation-is-prop {F = F} c-cat x y = path where
Representation-is-prop module X = Representation x
module Y = Representation y
: X.rep ≡ Y.rep
objs = c-cat .to-path (representation-unique x y)
objs
: x ≡ y
path .rep = objs i
path i .represents =
path i .≅-pathp refl (ap (よ₀ C) objs) {f = X.represents} {g = Y.represents}
C^(Nat-pathp _ _ λ a → Hom-pathp-reflr (Sets _)
{A = F .F₀ a} {q = λ i → el! (C.Hom a (objs i))}
(funext λ x →
(λ e → e .Sets.to) (ap-F₀-iso (Hom-from C a) c-cat _) $ₚ _
ap (Y.rep.to .is-natural _ _ _) $ₚ _
·· sym .Rep.from (sym (X.rep.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _)
·· ap Y.Rep.to (C.idl _)
·· ap X.Rep.ε _)))
·· X i
As terminal objects🔗
We begin to connect the idea of representing objects to other universal constructions by proving this alternative characterisation of representations: A functor is representable if, and only if, its category of elements has a terminal object.
terminal-element→representation: {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)}
→ Terminal (∫ C F) → Representation F
{F} term = f-rep where
terminal-element→representation module F = Functor F
open Terminal term
From the terminal object in 1, we obtain a natural transformation given componentwise by interpreting each pair as an object of then taking the terminating morphism which satisfies (by definition) This natural transformation is componentwise invertible, as the calculation below shows, so it constitutes a natural isomorphism.
: F => よ₀ C (top .ob)
nat .η ob section = has⊤ (elem ob section) .centre .hom
nat .is-natural x y f = funext λ sect → ap hom $ has⊤ _ .paths $ elem-hom _ $
nat .₁ (has⊤ _ .centre .hom C.∘ f) (top .section) ≡⟨ happly (F.F-∘ _ _) _ ⟩
F.₁ f (F.₁ (has⊤ _ .centre .hom) (top .section)) ≡⟨ ap (F.₁ f) (has⊤ _ .centre .commute) ⟩
F.₁ f sect ∎
F
: ∀ x → Sets.is-invertible (nat .η x)
inv = Sets.make-invertible
inv x (λ f → F.₁ f (top .section))
(funext λ x → ap hom $ has⊤ _ .paths (elem-hom x refl))
(funext λ x → has⊤ _ .centre .commute)
: Representation F
f-rep .rep = top .ob
f-rep .represents = C^.invertible→iso nat $
f-rep invertible→invertibleⁿ nat inv
In the other direction, we take the terminal element to be the image of the identity on the representing object.
representation→terminal-element: {F : Functor (C ^op) (Sets κ)}
→ Representation F → Terminal (∫ C F)
{F} F-rep = term where
representation→terminal-element module F = Functor F
module R = rep F-rep
open Terminal
: Terminal (∫ C F)
term .top .ob = F-rep .rep
term .top .section = R.from .η _ C.id
term .has⊤ (elem o s) .centre .hom = R.to .η _ s
term .has⊤ (elem o s) .centre .commute =
term .₁ (R.to .η o s) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡˘⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩
F.from .η _ ⌜ C.id C.∘ R.to .η o s ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (C.idl _) ⟩
R.from .η _ (R.to .η o s) ≡⟨ unext R.invr o s ⟩
R
s ∎.has⊤ (elem o s) .paths h = ext $
term .to .η o ⌜ s ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ comm ⟩
R.to .η o (R.from .η _ (h .hom)) ≡⟨ unext R.invl o _ ⟩
R.hom ∎
h where
=
comm .from .η _ ⌜ h .hom ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ (C.idl _) ⟩
R.from .η _ (C.id C.∘ h .hom) ≡⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩
R.₁ (h .hom) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡⟨ h .commute ⟩
F s ∎
Universal constructions🔗
In particular, we can show that terminal objects are representing objects for a particular functor. Consider, to be more specific, the constant functor which sends everything to the terminal set. When is representable?
Well, unfolding the definition, it’s when we have an object with a natural isomorphism Unfolding that, it’s an object for which, given any other object we have an isomorphism of sets 2. Hence, a representing object for the “constantly ” functor is precisely a terminal object.
representable-unit→terminal: Representation (Const (el (Lift _ ⊤) (hlevel 2))) → Terminal C
.Terminal.top = repr .rep
representable-unit→terminal repr .Terminal.has⊤ ob = retract→is-contr
representable-unit→terminal repr (Rep.from repr) (λ _ → lift tt) (Rep.η repr) (hlevel 0)
This can be seen as a special case of the construction above: is representable just when its category of elements has a terminal object, but in this case the category of elements of is just
Corepresentable functors🔗
As noted earlier, we can dualise the definition of a representable functor to the covariant setting to get corepresentable functors.
record Corepresentation (F : Functor C (Sets κ)) : Type (o ⊔ κ) where
no-eta-equality
field
: C.Ob
corep : F ≅ⁿ Hom-from C corep
corepresents
module corep = Isoⁿ corepresents
: ∀ {a} → C.Hom corep a ≃ F ʻ a
coequiv = Equiv.inverse (natural-iso→equiv corepresents _)
coequiv
module Corep {a} = Equiv (coequiv {a})
open Corepresentation
open Corepresentation using (module Corep) public
Much like their contravariant cousins, corepresenting objects are unique up to isomorphism.
corepresentation-unique: {F : Functor C (Sets κ)} (X Y : Corepresentation F)
→ X .corep C.≅ Y .corep
We omit the proof, as it is identical to the representable case.
=
corepresentation-unique X Y {F = Functor.op (よcov C)}
is-ff→essentially-injective (よcov-is-fully-faithful C)
(iso→co-iso (Cat[ C , Sets κ ]) ni)
where
: Hom-from C (Y .corep) ≅ⁿ Hom-from C (X .corep)
ni = (Y .corepresents ni⁻¹) ∘ni X .corepresents ni
This implies that the type of corepresentations is a proposition when is univalent.
: ∀ {F} → is-category C → is-prop (Corepresentation F) Corepresentation-is-prop
We opt to not show the proof, as it is even nastier than the proof for representables due to the fact that the yoneda embedding for covariant functors is itself contravariant.
{F = F} c-cat X Y = path where
Corepresentation-is-prop
: X .corep ≡ Y .corep
objs = c-cat .to-path (corepresentation-unique X Y)
objs
: X ≡ Y
path .corep = objs i
path i .corepresents =
path i .≅-pathp refl (ap (Hom-from C) objs)
[C,Sets]{f = X .corepresents} {g = Y .corepresents}
(Nat-pathp _ _ λ a → Hom-pathp-reflr (Sets _)
{A = F .F₀ a} {q = λ i → el! (C.Hom (objs i) a)}
(funext λ x →
(λ e → e .Sets.to) (ap-F₀-iso (Hom-into C a) (opposite-is-category c-cat) _) $ₚ _
ap (corep.to Y .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _)
·· sym (Corep.from Y) (sym (corep.from X .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _)
·· ap (Corep.to X) (C.idr _)
·· ap .ε X _)))
·· Corep i
Dualising the representable case, we have that a functor is corepresentable if and only if its covariant category of elements has an initial object.
initial-element→corepresentation: {F : Functor C (Sets κ)}
→ Initial (Co.∫ F) → Corepresentation F
corepresentation→initial-element: {F : Functor C (Sets κ)}
→ Corepresentation F → Initial (Co.∫ F)
The proofs are again entirely analogous to the representable case.
{F} init = f-corep where
initial-element→corepresentation module F = Functor F
open Initial init
open Co.Element
open Co.Element-hom
: F => Hom-from C (bot .ob)
nat .η ob section = has⊥ (Co.elem ob section) .centre .hom
nat .is-natural x y f = funext λ sect → ap hom $ has⊥ _ .paths $ Co.elem-hom _ $
nat .₁ (f C.∘ has⊥ _ .centre .hom) (bot .section) ≡⟨ happly (F.F-∘ _ _) _ ⟩
F.₁ f (F.₁ (has⊥ _ .centre .hom) (bot .section)) ≡⟨ ap (F.₁ f) (has⊥ _ .centre .commute) ⟩
F.₁ f sect ∎
F
: ∀ x → Sets.is-invertible (nat .η x)
inv = Sets.make-invertible
inv x (λ f → F.₁ f (bot .section))
(funext λ x → ap hom $ has⊥ _ .paths (Co.elem-hom x refl))
(funext λ x → has⊥ _ .centre .commute)
: Corepresentation F
f-corep .corep = bot .ob
f-corep .corepresents = [C,Sets].invertible→iso nat $
f-corep
invertible→invertibleⁿ nat inv
{F} F-corep = init where
corepresentation→initial-element module F = Functor F
module R = corep F-corep
open Initial
open Co.Element
open Co.Element-hom
: Initial (Co.∫ F)
init .bot .ob = F-corep .corep
init .bot .section = R.from .η _ C.id
init .has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .centre .hom = R.to .η _ s
init .has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .centre .commute =
init .₁ (R.to .η o s) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡˘⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩
F.from .η _ ⌜ R.to .η o s C.∘ C.id ⌝ ≡⟨ ap! (C.idr _) ⟩
R.from .η _ (R.to .η o s) ≡⟨ unext R.invr o s ⟩
R
s ∎.has⊥ (Co.elem o s) .paths h = ext $
init .to .η o ⌜ s ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ comm ⟩
R.to .η o (R.from .η _ (h .hom)) ≡⟨ unext R.invl o _ ⟩
R.hom ∎
h where
=
comm .from .η _ ⌜ h .hom ⌝ ≡˘⟨ ap¡ (C.idr _) ⟩
R.from .η _ (h .hom C.∘ C.id) ≡⟨ R.from .is-natural _ _ _ $ₚ _ ⟩
R.₁ (h .hom) (R.from .η _ C.id) ≡⟨ h .commute ⟩
F s ∎
Corepresentable functors preserve limits🔗
A useful fact about corepresentable functors is that they preserve all limits. To show this, we first need to show that the covariant hom functor preserves limits.
To get an intuition for why this is true, consider how the functor
behaves on products. The set of morphisms
is equivalent to the set
of pairs of morphisms (See product-repr
for a proof of this equivalence).
Hom-from-preserves-limits: ∀ {o' κ'}
→ (c : C.Ob)
→ is-continuous o' κ' (Hom-from C c)
{Diagram = Dia} {K} {eps} lim =
Hom-from-preserves-limits c (funext λ _ → refl) where
to-is-limitp ml open make-is-limit
module lim = is-limit lim
: make-is-limit _ _
ml .ψ j f = lim.ψ j C.∘ f
ml .commutes f = funext λ g →
ml .pulll (sym (eps .is-natural _ _ _))
C(C.elimr (K .F-id) C.⟩∘⟨refl)
∙ .universal eps p x =
ml .universal (λ j → eps j x) (λ f → p f $ₚ x)
lim.factors _ _ = funext λ _ →
ml .factors _ _
lim.unique eps p other q = funext λ x →
ml .unique _ _ _ λ j → q j $ₚ x lim
Preservation of limits by corepresentable functors then follows from a general fact about functors: if preserves limits, and is naturally isomorphic to then must also preserve limits.
corepresentable-preserves-limits: ∀ {o' κ'} {F}
→ Corepresentation F
→ is-continuous o' κ' F
=
corepresentable-preserves-limits F-corep lim
natural-iso→preserves-limits(F-corep .corepresents ni⁻¹)
(Hom-from-preserves-limits (F-corep .corep))
lim
We can show a similar fact for representable functors, but with a twist: they reverse colimits! This is due to the fact that a representable functor is contravariant. Specifically, will take limits in to limits in but limits in are colimits, so will take colimits in to limits in
A less formal perspective on this is that the collection of maps out of a colimit is still defined as a limit in For instance, to give a out of a coproduct, we are required to give a pair of maps and
よ-reverses-colimits: ∀ {o' κ'}
→ (c : C.Ob)
→ is-cocontinuous o' κ' (Functor.op (よ₀ C c))
{Diagram = Dia} {K} {eta} colim =
よ-reverses-colimits c (funext λ _ → refl) where
to-is-colimitp mc open make-is-colimit
module colim = is-colimit colim
: make-is-colimit _ _
mc .ψ j f = f C.∘ colim.ψ j
mc .commutes f = funext λ g →
mc .pullr (eta .is-natural _ _ _)
C(C.refl⟩∘⟨ C.eliml (K .F-id))
∙ .universal eta p x =
mc .universal (λ j → eta j x) (λ f → p f $ₚ x)
colim.factors eta p = funext λ _ →
mc .factors _ _
colim.unique eta p other q = funext λ x →
mc .unique _ _ _ λ j → q j $ₚ x
colim
representable-reverses-colimits: ∀ {o' κ'} {F}
→ Representation F
→ is-cocontinuous o' κ' (Functor.op F)
=
representable-reverses-colimits F-rep colim
natural-iso→preserves-colimits((F-rep .represents ni^op) ni⁻¹)
(よ-reverses-colimits (F-rep .rep))
colim