module Cat.Instances.Discrete where
Discrete categoriesπ
Given a groupoid , we can build the category with space of objects and a single morphism whenever .
: (A : Type β) β is-groupoid A β Precategory β β
Disc .Ob = A
Disc A A-grpd .Hom = _β‘_
Disc A A-grpd .Hom-set = A-grpd
Disc A A-grpd .id = refl
Disc A A-grpd ._β_ p q = q β p
Disc A A-grpd .idr _ = β-idl _
Disc A A-grpd .idl _ = β-idr _
Disc A A-grpd .assoc _ _ _ = sym (β-assoc _ _ _)
Disc A A-grpd
: Set β β Precategory β β
Disc' = Disc β£ A β£ h where abstract
Disc' A : is-groupoid β£ A β£
h = is-hlevel-suc 2 (A .is-tr) h
Clearly this is a univalent groupoid:
: β {A : Type β} {A-grpd} β is-category (Disc A A-grpd)
Disc-is-category .to-path is = is .to
Disc-is-category .to-path-over is = β
-pathp _ _ _ Ξ» i j β is .to (i β§ j)
Disc-is-category
: β {A : Type β} {A-grpd} β is-pregroupoid (Disc A A-grpd)
Disc-is-groupoid = make-invertible _ (sym p) (β-invl p) (β-invr p) Disc-is-groupoid p
We can lift any function between the underlying types to a functor between discrete categories. This is because every function automatically respects equality in a functorial way.
lift-disc: β {A : Set β} {B : Set β'}
β (β£ A β£ β β£ B β£)
β Functor (Disc' A) (Disc' B)
.Fβ = f
lift-disc f .Fβ = ap f
lift-disc f .F-id = refl
lift-disc f .F-β p q = ap-β f q p lift-disc f
Diagrams in Disc(X)π
If
is a discrete type
, then it is in particular in
Set
, and we
can make diagrams of shape
in some category
,
using the decidable equality on
.
We note that the decidable equality is redundant information:
The construction Disc'
above
extends into a left
adjoint to the Ob
functor.
Disc-diagram: β {X : Set β} β¦ _ : Discrete β£ X β£ β¦
β (β£ X β£ β Ob C)
β Functor (Disc' X) C
{C = C} {X = X} β¦ d β¦ f = F where
Disc-diagram module C = Precategory C
: β£ X β£ β β£ X β£ β Type _
P = C.Hom (f x) (f y)
P x y
: β {x y : β£ X β£} β x β‘ y β Dec (x β‘α΅’ y) β P x y
go {x} {.x} p (yes reflα΅’) = C.id
go {x} {y} p (no Β¬p) = absurd (Β¬p (Idβpath.from p)) go
The object part of the functor is the provided , and the decidable equality is used to prove that respects equality. This is why itβs redundant: automatically respects equality, because itβs a function! However, by using the decision procedure, we get better computational behaviour: Very often, will be , and substitution along is easy to deal with.
: Functor _ _
F .Fβ = f
F .Fβ {x} {y} p = go p (x β‘α΅’? y) F
Proving that our our is functorial involves a bunch of tedious computations with equalities and a whole waterfall of absurd cases:
.F-id {x} = refl
F .F-β {x} {y} {z} f g =
F (Ξ» y g β β {z} (f : y β‘ z) β go (g β f) (x β‘α΅’? z) β‘ go f (y β‘α΅’? z) C.β go g (x β‘α΅’? y))
J (Ξ» f β J (Ξ» z f β go (refl β f) (x β‘α΅’? z) β‘ go f (x β‘α΅’? z) C.β C.id) (sym (C.idr _)) f)
g f